'Proactionary' Principle Shows Limits of Precaution
A proactive approach to the health dangers inherent in technological progress is preferable to an excess of precaution, according to the Extropy Institute. The principles of Extropy show an optimistic outlook towards the future: Extropians see positive changes for humanity through technology, rational thinking and an open, transformative society that prefers freedom of individual action, rather than authoritative control.
On the opposing end of the scale, we find the precautionary principle, which favors inaction and restriction over action and innovation. Precaution has made large inroads into our legislative systems, setting ever more impossible-to-satisfy criteria for "proof of innocence" of new technologies, for even such basic things as nutritional supplementation. Under the precautionary principle, vital nutrients without which our bodies cease to function, must now prove that they are innocent, which means they must prove that they are completely harmless even if we eat them every day of our lives. What happened to sanity and balance, we might ask.
As a counter-weight to the stifling influence of such exaggerated precaution on progress, the Extropy Institute is proposing that we should enact what it calls the proactionary principle. This proposed new way of evaluating technological progress advocates looking at all the evidence and weighing the consequences of both action and inaction, before deciding which way to go.
The proactionary principle is credited to Max More, Ph.D., and is largely based on discussions at the Extropy Institute's 2004 Vital Progress Summit.
- - -
The Proactionary Principle
"People's freedom to innovate technologically is highly valuable, even critical, to humanity. This implies several imperatives when restrictive measures are proposed: Assess risks and opportunities according to available science, not popular perception. Account for both the costs of the restrictions themselves, and those of opportunities foregone. Favor measures that are proportionate to the probability and magnitude of impacts, and that have a high expectation value. Protect people's freedom to experiment, innovate, and progress."Going just a bit more in depth, we find the proactionary principle to break down into these points:
1. People's freedom to innovate technologically is valuable to humanity. The burden of proof therefore belongs to those who propose restrictive measures. All proposed measures should be closely scrutinized.2. Evaluate risk according to available science, not popular perception, and allow for common reasoning biases.
3. Give precedence to ameliorating known and proven threats to human health and environmental quality over acting against hypothetical risks.
4. Treat technological risks on the same basis as natural risks; avoid underweighting natural risks and overweighting human-technological risks. Fully account for the benefits of technological advances.
5. Estimate the lost opportunities of abandoning a technology, and take into account the costs and risks of substituting other credible options, carefully considering widely distributed effects and follow-on effects.
6. Consider restrictive measures only if the potential impact of an activity has both significant probability and severity. In such cases, if the activity also generates benefits, discount the impacts according to the feasibility of adapting to the adverse effects. If measures to limit technological advance do appear justified, ensure that the extent of those measures is proportionate to the extent of the probable effects.
7. When choosing among measures to restrict technological innovation, prioritize decision criteria as follows: Give priority to risks to human and other intelligent life over risks to other species; give non-lethal threats to human health priority over threats limited to the environment (within reasonable limits); give priority to immediate threats over distant threats; prefer the measure with the highest expectation value by giving priority to more certain over less certain threats, and to irreversible or persistent impacts over transient impacts.
For a more full description, including a discussion of why this principle was developed to provide a counter-weight to the now ubiquitous precautionary principle, see this page on the Extropy Institute's site.
What about GM?
All well and good for nutrients and health options, you might say, but what about the dangers of such things as genetic modification or nanotechnology. We know that those are dangerous and a precautionary approach will keep us safe.
Well, not exactly. All the precautionary approach does is make us lazy in arguing our case. If we believe there are dangers in the application of a certain technology, we must argue the case ... and we better confront the proponents of that technology on a level of rational argument. What would be wrong about approaching the matter with an open mind, about looking at all the pros and cons and only then deciding?
Yes, there can be abuse on both sides - notably a refusal to see the other side's arguments. Perhaps we need to overcome the highly divisive force of the precautionary principle, which skews things in a one-sided way actually preventing rational argument and decision-making.
How did we get into this mess?
It is the old blame game. When something goes wrong, we seek to assign blame for what happened, instead of working to find out where we made a mistake and fixing it. The press has a large part in this.
A prime example in my book is BSE or mad cow disease. When BSE appeared in Europe, there was a huge outcry of blame - without anyone really finding the cause of the problem. The result: Legislators and administrators scrambled to "cover their backsides" and the precautionary principle was a great candidate to achieve that security. It gives administrators the power to intervene early and heavy to make double sure no such scandal could ever erupt again. Risk can be all but eliminated.
But we are now seeing that good cover for a bureaucrat's backside is not everything. We must go on living, but we find our spaces for individual decisions and our prospects for progress to be greatly reduced. Risk is an integral part of life. If we were to avoid all risk, we would also never get to progress beyond our current state. So why not abolish this current emphasis on precaution in favor of a more balanced approach such as the one we find in the proactionary principle.
Links:
Wikipedia on the Precautionary principle
posted by Sepp Hasslberger on Wednesday October 25 2006
URL of this article:
http://www.newmediaexplorer.org/sepp/2006/10/25/proactionary_principle_shows_limits_of_precaution.htm
Related ArticlesRisk Free Vitamins - How Safe is Safe Enough?
Recent legislative proposals on at least three continents have centered around the perceived need to ensure the safety of natural health products, such as supplements containing vitamins and minerals. Canada has proposed drug-style regulations for supplements. In the US, a proposal termed S 722 seeks to increase the FDA's powers to remove supplements from circulation. Australia recalled 1600 diverse health products in an unprecedented prelude to - what else -... [read more]
February 03, 2004 - Sepp HasslbergerSupplements: Consumer Advocates, Scientists, Criticize EU Approach
The European Commission issued a discussion paper earlier this year, asking for input from interested parties regarding the details of how to cap nutrient dosage levels in foods and nutritional supplements. At the time, Paul Taylor, a consumer advocate who lives in the UK, commented: The Health and Consumer Protection Directorate-General states that it is keen to obtain the view of stakeholders on how these issues might be addressed and... [read more]
October 03, 2006 - Sepp HasslbergerCodex: WHO/FAO Told Nutrient Risk Assessment Must Consider Benefits
In a submission to the FAO/WHO nutrient risk assessment project, Dr. Robert Verkerk, Director of the Alliance for Natural Health charges that assessment of the possible risks of nutrient overdose must also consider the beneficial effects of nutrients. He says that risk assessments undertaken to date "are not based on a sufficiently rational scientific platform" and "will provide misleading information for policy decision-makers". At stake is the continued availability of... [read more]
December 16, 2004 - Sepp HasslbergerManaging Risk Perception - Trust and Transparency
At a recent conference in Brussels, Commissioner David Byrne who is holding the health and consumer protection portfolio, addressed the participants on the subject of risk perception. Byrne seems baffled why some risks seem to be quite acceptable, while others are perceived as severe. To my mind, the Commission is dishonest if it wants to influence risk perception by the public, while refusing to handle the MAJOR risks in our... [read more]
December 06, 2003 - Sepp HasslbergerEU Commissioner Byrne: No Zero Risk Society
In a recent seminar on public risk perception, the EU's Health and Consumer Affairs Commissioner David Byrne made a revealing statement. He told us that there is no such thing as a zero risk society. While I agree with what he says, I find it interesting that this statement comes at a time when the EU is discussing controls of toxic chemicals and when there is pressure from the chemical... [read more]
March 31, 2004 - Sepp HasslbergerFood Supplements: Too Much Precaution May Be Bad For Your Health
After the passage, in 2002, of Europe-wide regulations for food supplements, the Alliance for Natural Health has argued before the European Court of Justice that vitamin and mineral supplements are innocent - not to be condemned or worse eradicated by bureaucratic red tape. The court decided in July 2005, surprisingly disregarding the opinion of its own Advocate general, who had called for the directive to be declared illegitimate, commenting that... [read more]
October 13, 2005 - Sepp Hasslberger